Excerpts from
Overruling Democracy: The Supreme Court vs. The American People

The following are excerpts from Overruling
Democracy: The Supreme Court vs. The American People, a 2003 book (Taylor & Francis Books,
Inc.) by Washington College of Law professor Jamin Raskin and a
member of the Center for Voting and Democracy's advisory committee.
He presents a broad pro-democracy agenda, including instant runoff
voting and full representation (here called "proportional
representation.") Below are two excerpts: the first about the case
for full representation and the
second about using instant runoff
voting
when electing the president.
Representing Everyone: Proportional
Representation (229-234)
Most of the issues addressed in the
constitution amendments I proffer above are ���first generation���
voting issues. They have to do with people being able to cast
ballots and get them counted; with the people as a collective
enjoying the basic right of majority rule; and with young people
having a right to receive an education for democratic citizenship.
The question of legislative proportional representation is a kind of
second-generation structural issue, a background rule-setting
question that grows in importance as we resolve the pressing
first-generation problems.[14] Indeed, proportional representation is
fast moving from being a curious idea to an urgent democratic
imperative.[15] Both democracy and equality tell us that public
office must be open to all.[16] Beyond democracy and equal
opportunity, in contemporary American politics another kind of
interest compels us to hold the door of public office open: this is
the political legitimacy achieved when all citizens have in
government political leaders who actually represent them, their
values, their lives and concerns. President Clinton spoke to this
felt need in the country when he said that he wanted to build an
administration that ���looks like America.���[17] It might improve this
democratic sentiment a bit to say that we should seek a government
that thinks and feels like America, although it is logical to
suppose that such a government would look like America, too. But the
looks of our leaders are a concern secondary to the outlooks of our
leaders, who should represent all of the people in our great
diversity of thoughts and values. The Courts doctrinal mess over
majority-minority districts creates a critical opportunity to push
for new rules to replace the chaos and unfairness of inescapable
arbitrary legislative district line-drawing. The public is about to
discover the advantages of proportional representation elections
methods, such as instant runoff voting (which is built into the
presidential election amendment), preference voting and the like.
Often the case for proportional representation is cast as an
argument to guarantee electoral minorities a voice. This argument,
though not exactly inaccurate, is radically incomplete, because it
misses the true virtue of proportional representation. The strong
argument for proportional systems, which was made by John Stuart
Mill in 1861,[18] is that they empower the vast majority of people to
be represented and active. Consider a state with ten U.S. House
seats where 60 percent of the people belong to Party A, 30 percent
to Party B, and 10 percent to Party C. Assuming an even partisan
distribution of voters across the state, in an election, Party A
will capture all of the House seats, meaning that 60 percent of the
voters will have 100 percent of the representation, and 40 percent
will get none at all. This is an especially dramatic problem when
only half the people turn out to vote, which means, in this
hypothetical case, that 30 percent of the electorate is winning 100
percent of the representation. If we switch to a system of
cumulative voting or preference voting, we would instead expect
Party A to capture six of the state���s House seats, Party B to win
three of them and Party C one. Thus by overthrowing a
winner-take-all single-member district regime and replacing it with
proportional representation, we have actually given the entire
population of the state some representative voice and agency in
Congress. This brings democratic politics into line with a powerful
majoritarian principle. The clean one-party sweep of congressional
delegations is no imaginary thing. In Utah, Idaho and Alaska, for
example, Republicans have every Senate and House seat, meaning that
Democrats, Greens, and Independents in those states have no partisan
representation in Washington. Similarly, in Massachusetts and Rhode
Island, Democrats have all the Senate and House seats, leaving the
substantial parts of the population registered to other parties
without any ascriptive partisan representation over time. In truth,
most congressional districts in America include large numbers of
citizens who continue to vote for losing parties and candidates and
grow increasingly disgruntled over time. The Center for Voting and
Democracy can safely predict the party affiliation of the winner in
more than 90 percent of U.S. House districts a year before the
elections because the vast majority of districts are
partisan-gerrymandered and safely in the Democratic and Republican
column. Those incumbents essentially get to design their own
districts and then, as presumptive winners and officeholders,
consolidate their huge fund-raising advantage over opponents. In
2000, 90 percent of House incumbents won by at least 10 percent of
the vote and most won by substantially more than that. Political
analyst Charles Cook tells us that, after the 2000 census and
redistricting process, fewer than 50 out of 435 House seats are
truly competitive.[19] As the Economist puts it, redistricting has
become a ���glorified incumbent-protection racket.���[20] It would be
easy enough to cast aside this hopelessly stacked, winner-take-all,
zero sum regime by using the state���s apportionment of House seats in
a way to maximize the whole public���s ability to see someone they
support elected. If Maryland has eight U.S. House seats, these
members should be elected statewide using a system of preference or
cumulative voting. It would essentially take one eighth of the votes
cast statewide to win, rather than 50 percent plus one in a
district. This is the way most of the world does it, and it holds
major advantages in terms of voter turn out and participation over
single-member districts, which produce a lot of frozen-out and
despondent voters over time.[21] Indeed, although we know the
decision is not supposed to have precedential effect, Bush v. Gore
invites us to wonder whether there is an Equal Protection violation
when a voter in a 60-percent bloc ends up having a partisan affinity
with 100 percent of the state���s delegation and a voter in the
40-percent bloc ends up with no effective representation. What about
a virtual tie in a presidential election, where a few hundred votes
out of millions cast make the difference between getting 25
Electoral College votes and zero? Is this really treating each vote
equally? Another brewing problem which militates in favor of
proportional representation arises from close population equality
among congressional districts within a state; in disparities among
districts and essentially required exactly equal populations. Yet
because of standard population movement and demographic changes,
there are always huge disparities by the end of a decade following a
reapportionment. Thus according to Rob Richie, several districts at
the end of 1990s had more than 200,000 voters above the
constitutional requirement in their states. Statewide proportional
voting would prevent these inevitable departures from the otherwise
scrupulous one person, one vote norm by liberating congressional
elections from the vagaries of single-member districting. There is
nothing in the Constitution stopping states from choosing House
members or state legislators along proportional lines in at-large
elections. But federal law since 1967 has required states to use
single-member districts.[23] This was, ironically, a Civil Rights
measure designed to protect the Voting Rights Act of 1965 by
preventing Southern states from using winner-take-all, at-large
districts not to spread representation out proportionally but rather
to render an effective black vote impossible. Before her defeat in
2002, Congresswoman Cynthia McKinney, an African-American
representative from Georgia who favored proportional representation
methods, introduced legislation to permit at-large elections in
conjunction with cumulative voting, limited voting or preference
voting. Such at-large elections would promote rather than undermine
the representational purposes of the Voting Rights Act. There are
numerous examples of successful use of proportional systems, such as
Illinois���s famous 110-year-run with cumulative voting and the
preference voting system employed by Cambridge, Massachusetts.[24]
Notice that this is more robust and expansive political
representation need not be defined exclusively or primarily in
racial or ethnic terms. The reflexive assumption that group
representation necessarily means representation on the basis of race
or ethnicity reflects the mental prison we have constructed from our
racial past. People should be able to elect leaders who effectively
represent their politics, moral values, ethical perspectives, social
commitments, cultural attitudes, economic interests and local
agendas. One of the great losses of the Clinton period was President
Clinton���s decision to nominate but then cut loose Professor Lani
Guinier as assistant attorney general for civil rights. Professor
Guinier is a leading champion of proportional political
representation but was singled out and slammed by right-wingers as a
���quota queen,���[25] which is outrageous since proportional
representation is rooted in the idea that voters should be able to
group themselves as they please. Its practice would eliminate the
power of state legislators to design districts for racist purposes,
incumbent self-protection or partisan manipulation. The
neoconservative witch-hunt against Professor Guinier remains a
disgraceful case of intellectual racial profiling. Sometimes
people���s voting belief systems will overlap and correlate with their
racial, ethnic and religious identities and those of their preferred
candidates. For example, when Congressman Harold Washington, an
African American, ran for mayor of Chicago in 1983, he received
overwhelming support form other African Americans because they
believed that he would champion the interests of citizens who had
been victimized by racism and the exclusionary machine politics of
the city. In Maryland, however, overwhelming numbers of African
Americans voted in 1988 and 1992 for the distinguished progressive
Senator Paul Sarbanes (who is white) and feisty Senator Barbara
Mikulski (also white) against ultraconservative African-American
Republican Alan Keyes, who would later run for president. In
Washington, D.C., a majority-African-American city, the public has
elected an African-American mayor ever since modern home rule was
granted in 1974, but the city also repeatedly elected a white
politician, the late David Clarke, to be chairman of its council.
Clarke, a committed progressive with deep roots in the Civil Rights
movement, repeatedly won huge support in the black community against
several African-American opponents. Today a gay white Republican
councilmember, David Catania, has strong support in the
African-American community. Thus nothing compels whites to vote for
whites, African-Americans for African-Americans, Asian Americans for
Asian Americans, Hispanics for Hispanics and so on. Such a primitive
voting system appeals to the lowest common denominator, which in
American society has been racism, specifically the toxic
ramifications of white supremacy. Everything politically progressive
in our history, from abolitionism in the 1850s to populism in the
1890s to the unionism of the 1930s to the Student nonviolent
Coordinating Committee and other Civil Rights groups in the 1960s to
the Rainbow Coalition of the 1980s, has argued for interracial
political coalition against balkanized, group-thick racial politics.
But racial polarization and organization have obviously had a
powerful influence on our political development, especially given
the ubiquity of single-member districts and patterns of white bloc
voting in the South and elsewhere.[26] As recently as the 1980s, for
example in ���the majority of southern states, not a single
majority-white district elected a black legislator,���[27] and this
basic pattern of racially polarized voting continues today in major
parts of the country. Professors Lanu Guinier and Gerald Torres
have championed the virtues of proportional representation methods
over winner-take-all systems and have made a subtle argument for the
use of what they call ���political race.���[28] By this they mean
organizing people not along the lines of essentialized racial
identity politics but around the lived experience of having been
oppressed by race and yet influenced as well by a corresponding
politics of social solidarity and community. These experiences can
sustain the practical and visionary political hope for building an
interracial society that addresses everyone���s real needs.
Understanding the risks of race-based politics, they emphasize that
���use of race as a political category gains its legitimacy from its
promise to increase the quantum of democracy in society and to
resist unfair concentrations of wealth and power.���[29] They thus
embrace ���the possibility of using race and politics to create an
identity that resists conventional categories and supports
democratic renewal.���[30] Theirs is a kind of strategic-democratic
politics that could make a movement for broad constitutional change
nationally a movement for deep social change locally.
14 This is the
aspect of power that theorist John Gaventa considers ���second
dimension��� because it concerns the structuring of background rules
to produce particular kinds of political outcomes. Gaventa contrasts
this with ���first dimension��� exercises of power which involve A more
directly causing B to do B something would rather not do. The ���third
dimension��� of power relates to the deployment of power through
ideology and culture. See John Gaventa. ���Power and Participation,���
in Power and Powerlessness: Quiescence and Rebellion in an
Appalachian Valley (1980). I am indebted to Professor Gerald Frug
for assigning Gaventa���s essay as homework in my Local Government Law
class when I was in law school. It had a profound effect on me.
15 See Steven Hill, Fixing Elections: The Failure of America���s
Winner Take All Politics (2002, for a lucid and authoritative
argument for proportional representation. 16 Democracy insists
that the people be able to choose freely their own leaders, and
equal opportunity demands that each citizen has a chance to
experience political leadership. Madison had something like this in
mind when he wrote about the congressional Qualifications Clauses in
The Federalist: ���Who are to be the objects of popular choice? Every
citizen whose merit may recommend him to the esteem and confidence
of his country. No qualification of wealth, of birth, of religious
faith, or of civil profession is permitted to fetter the judgment or
disappoint the inclination of the people.��� Madison, The Federalist
No. 57 at 351
17 Speeches
given during presidential campaign, 1991-1992.
18 J.S. Mill,
Representative Government (1861).
19
���Congressional Redistricting: How to Rig an Election,��� The
Economist, April 27, 2002.
20 Id
21 A thorough
and nuanced argument for proportional representation appears in
Robert Richie and Steven Hill, Reflecting All of Us: The Case for
Proportional Representation (1999).
23 Act of
December 14, 1967, Pub. L. No. 90-196, 81 Stat. 581. The first
statutory requirement for single-member districts was embodied in an
1842 statute (5 Stat. 491) which provided that representative
���should be elected by districts composed of contiguous territory
equal in number to the number of representatives to which said state
may be entitled, no one district electing more than one
representative.��� An 1850 apportionment statute (9 Stat. 433) got rid
of the single-member district requirement and Congress continued to
see-saw on the issue.
24 See Steven
Hill, Fixing Elections: The Failure of America���s Winner Take All
Politics 35 (2002).
25 See op-ed by
Clint Bolick, Wall Street Journal, April 30, 1993.
26 For extensive
statistical evidence about racially polarized white-bloc voting in
the South, see Grofman, Handley and Niemi, Minority Representation
and the Quest for Voting Equality; Chandler Davidson and Bernard
Grofman, Quiet Revolution in the South: The Impact of the Voting
Rights Act of 1965-1990.
27 Davidson and
Grofman at 338.
28 Lani Guinier
and Gerald Torres, The Miner���s Canary: Enlisting Race, Resisting
Power, Transforming Democracy (2002). See also Douglas Amy, Real
Choices, New Voices: The Case for Proportional Representation
Elections in the United States, Columbia Univ. Press, 1995.
29 Guinier and
Torres at 252.
30 Id. at 253.
The Popular Election of
the President Amendment (64-66)
Consider the following
amendment to adopt direct popular election of the president which
includes a built-in ���instant run-off��� provision to guarantee that
the winner actually has majority support of the voters: The
President and the Vice President shall be elected by direct popular
vote of all U.S. Citizens eighteen years of age and older, but no
person shall be elected President who has not attained at least 50
percent support among the votes cast. Whenever there are three or
more candidates listed on the ballot, the ballot shall ask voters to
rank their choices in order of preference. If no candidate receives
at least 50 percent of the first-place votes cast, the last place
candidate���s ballots shall be redistributed to the second-choice
candidates of these voters. This instant runoff method shall
continue until a candidate has achieved a majority of all votes
cast. Of the several important changes embodied in this Popular
Election of the President Amendment, the enactment of majority rule
is only the most obvious�ĶThe Popular Election of the President
Amendment replaces the bizarre Rube Goldberg-type contraptions of
the electoral college ��� the two-vote add-on, the lengthy delays
between popular voting and the casting of the electoral-college
votes, the contingent House election based on state-by-state voting,
the recurring possibilities of popular-vote losers winning the
election ��� with clean and simple majority rule. A majority is
guaranteed by virtue of the ���instant runoff��� mechanism, which
assures that the winner will achieve a popular mandate without
requiring that an expensive second (or third) runoff election be
held. This method of voting not only guarantees that candidates will
take office with majority support but also dampens partisan
invective and rancor during the campaign. Candidates have no
interest in polarizing things because they want to become a group of
voters��� second favored choice even if they cannot be their first.
This instant runoff mechanism is gaining increasing support around
the country. On March 5, 2002, the people of San Francisco voted by
56 percent to 44 percent to adopt instant runoff voting for election
of local officials. Rob Richie and Steven Hill of the Center for
Voting and Democracy in Takoma Park, Maryland, who organized the
drive, have made a signal contribution to public discourse by
putting the instant runoff on America���s democracy agenda.
|